health problem related to maternal and infant health- 2 page
SCIENTIFIC CONTRIBUTION
Complexity and indeterminism of evidence-based public health: an analytical framework
Francesco Attena
Published online: 16 March 2014
� Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014
Abstract Improving the evidence in public health is an
important goal for the health promotion community. With
better evidence, health professionals can make better
decisions to achieve effectiveness in their interventions.
The relative failure of such evidence in public health is
well-known, and it is due to several factors. Briefly, from
an epistemological point of view, it is not easy to develop
evidence-based public health because public health inter-
ventions are highly complex and indeterminate. This paper
proposes an analytical explanation of the complexity and
indeterminacy of public health interventions in terms of 12
points. Public health interventions are considered as a
causal chain constituted by three elements (intervention,
risk factor, and disease) and two levels of evaluation (risk
factor and disease). Public health interventions thus differ
from clinical interventions, which comprise two causal
elements and one level of evaluation. From the two levels
of evaluation, we suggest a classification of evidence into
four typologies: evidence of both relations; evidence of the
second (disease) but not of the first (risk factor) relation;
evidence of the first but not of the second relation; and no
evidence of either relation. In addition, a grading of inde-
terminacy of public health interventions is introduced. This
theoretical point of view could be useful for public health
professionals to better define and classify the public health
interventions before acting.
Keywords Causality � Complexity � Epidemiology � Epistemology � Public health
Introduction
Public health interventions, complexity, and indeterminism
are strictly interrelated concepts. Briefly, public health
interventions are considered health and epidemiological
activities of high complexity. The main epistemological
feature of these complex systems is their indeterminacy;
the indeterminism of complex systems represents a strong
limitation to the claim of evidence-based public health.
Evidence-based public health (EBPH)
Improving the evidence in public health is an important
goal for the health promotion community. With better
evidence, health professionals can make better decisions
to achieve effectiveness in their interventions. EBPH is
‘‘the conscientious, explicit, and judicious use of current
best evidence in making decisions about the care of
communities and populations in the domain of health
protection, disease prevention, health maintenance and
improvement’’ (Jenicek 1997). In more recent years, the
perspectives of community members have been included,
which has helped foster a more population-centered
approach (Brownson et al. 2009); thus, EBPH has also
become ‘‘a process of integrating science-based inter-
ventions with community preferences to improve the
health of populations’’ (Kohatsu et al. 2004). Some crit-
ical points related to EBPH are as follows: What kind of
evidence is it possible to produce with regard to both
observational and experimental studies? How should this
evidence be graded (Tang et al. 2008)? How should this
evidence be translated into public health practice and
have a bearing on the decision-making process (Rychetnik
et al. 2012)? And how should this whole process of
EBPH be constructed (Briss et al. 2000)?
F. Attena (&) Second University of Naples, Naples, Italy
e-mail: francesco.attena@unina2.it
123
Med Health Care and Philos (2014) 17:459–465
DOI 10.1007/s11019-014-9554-0
Complexity
The concept of complexity is elusive and with uncertain
boundaries. It can be defined as ‘‘a scientific theory which
asserts that some systems display behavioral phenomena
that are completely inexplicable by any conventional ana-
lysis of the systems’ constituent parts’’ (Hawe et al. 2004).
More particularly, the complex systems ‘‘are highly com-
posite ones, built up from very large numbers of mutually
interacting subunits (that are often composites themselves)
whose repeated interactions result in rich, collective
behavior that feeds back into the behavior of the individual
parts’’ (Rickles et al. 2007).
For the purpose of this paper, we consider the following
characteristics of complex systems (Plsek and Greenhalgh
2001; Pearce and Merletti 2006; Galea et al. 2010;
Tremblay and Richard 2011): the large number of inter-
acting components; self-organization; circular causality or
feedback; and emergent properties. The indeterminism of
complex systems and their unpredictability are the episte-
mological consequences of these properties.
Complex systems differ from complicated systems. The
latter also have many interacting components, but they
interact in a mechanistic manner (mechanical causality), in
which the whole is equal to the sum of their parts and
where the rules are linear causality and predictability.
Computers and airplanes are very complicated—but not
complex—systems because they must have strictly pre-
dictable behaviors. Therefore, whereas public health
interventions are closer to complex systems, clinical
interventions are less complex, having characteristics more
similar to those of complicated systems (Attena 1999).
Clinical interventions might be also more complicated than
public health interventions, but they must be less complex
(i.e. more binding, deterministic and predictive) because
they deal with ill people who need, with a high degree of
certainty, to heal or improve their disease status. Public
health interventions are less bound to this requirement, and
they can afford a greater degree of error.
Indeterminism and unpredictability
As previously shown, if indeterminism is an epistemolog-
ical consequence of complexity, and public health inter-
ventions are highly complex systems, then public health
interventions involve a high level of indeterminacy. The
indeterminism of public health interventions may be
interpreted in two ways. According to epistemic indeter-
minism, seeming indeterminism is only a consequence of
the lack of knowledge about an underlying determinism
(chance due to ignorance). Ontological indeterminism, in
contrast, describes indeterminism as a real, ontological
characteristic of nature (chance lies in the nature of things).
After a long period of dominance by the deterministic point
of view beginning with Laplace’s demon, ontological
indeterminism became dominant among the physics com-
munity in relation to quantum theory. In the field of life
sciences, in contrast, epistemic indeterminism remained
implicitly dominant. Epistemic indeterminism may be
included in the wider conception of general determinism,
which states that ‘‘everything is determined in accordance
with laws by something else’’ (Bunge 1979). Owing to
complexity, the indeterminism of complex systems—and
consequently of public health interventions—is certainly
irreducible in principle. However, though it is very difficult
to determine whether the indeterminism is epistemic or
ontological, here the paradigm of epistemic indeterminism
is sustained.
Public health interventions involve a higher degree of
indeterminism than do clinical interventions. Furthermore,
for a given degree of indeterminism, the outcomes of
public health interventions present a given degree of
unpredictability, with scientific prediction defined as the
‘‘deduction of propositions concerning as yet unknown or
unexperienced facts, on the basis of general laws and of
items of specific information’’ (Bunge 1979). Moreover, if
the indeterminism is epistemic, even predictability has
epistemic significance, so it may be gradually reduced by
repeating experiments and improving methodologies.
To this point, these considerations about the controversy
between determinism and indeterminism have very much
concerned risk factor epidemiology (Susser 1973; Kar-
hausen 2000; Parascandola and Weed 2001; Olsen 2003;
Parascandola 2011).
This paper presents an analytical explanation of the
complexity, and consequently the indeterminism and the
unpredictability, that underlie public health interventions.
Then, starting from the characteristics of public health
interventions, four typologies of evidence are discussed.
Complexity of public health interventions
Public health interventions are intended to promote health
or prevent ill health in communities or populations (Ry-
chetnik et al. 2002). They are distinguished from clinical
interventions (mainly clinical trials), which are intended to
treat groups of ill people. Public health interventions
include a wide range of activities: policies, laws, and reg-
ulations; organizational or community developments;
education of individuals and communities; engineering and
technical developments; service development and delivery;
and communication, including social marketing (Rychetnik
et al. 2004). More synthetically, public health interventions
can be divided into three broad categories: clinical;
behavioral; and environmental.
460 F. Attena
123
Clinical prevention interventions are those conveyed by
health-care providers, often within a clinical setting (e.g.,
vaccines), and interventions using some kind of drug for
preventive purposes (e.g., statins in primary prevention).
They differ from clinical interventions because they
involve healthy people. Behavioral strategies include
health-promotion interventions, in which people are moti-
vated to modify unhealthy behavior (e.g., stopping smok-
ing). Environmental interventions are those that society can
impose by acting on the environment (e.g., water purifi-
cation) (Haddix et al. 1996). When a public health inter-
vention provides an evaluation of outcomes, we enter the
field of observational or experimental epidemiology. Both
within the context of observational and experimental epi-
demiology, the characteristics of public health interven-
tions with respect to clinical interventions—and
particularly with respect to randomized controlled trials
(RCTs)—are reported below and synthesized in Table 1.
Here, we largely make an evaluation of health-promotion
interventions, though sometimes also of environmental
ones. Clinical prevention interventions, which are similar
to clinical interventions, have been excluded.
Length of the causal chain
Theoretically, and with the exclusion of confounding fac-
tors, in clinical trials the causal chain is constituted by two
elements: the treatment or clinical intervention (cause) and
the outcome (effect). Sometimes, so-called intermediate
variables are considered and evaluated, such that the chain
can appear to comprise three elements. By contrast, in
public health interventions, the causal chain is fundamen-
tally constituted by three elements: the preventive inter-
vention, the risk factor, and the outcome. The intervention
(cause) acts on the risk factor (effect), and the risk factor
(cause) acts on the outcome (effect). To evaluate the
effectiveness of the intervention, it is possible to examine
the first and/or the second relation (Fig. 1).
Dual outcomes
The consequence is that the public health interventions
have two levels of evaluation—reduction of the risk factor,
and reduction of the corresponding disease. For example,
in a health-promotion intervention to reduce childhood
obesity by modifying the diet, evaluation can involve either
the intervention ability to modify the diet (first level) and/
or the reduction in obesity (second level). The choice to do
neither, one, or both evaluations depends on several fac-
tors, such as the degree of context dependence, the reli-
ability of causal relations, available resources, and whether
any experimental setting has been designed.
Weakness of the causal chain
Often despite extensive research efforts, both causal rela-
tions can be uncertain: the first one simply because of the
characteristics of indeterminacy and unpredictability of
public health interventions outlined above; the second one
for the well-known limitations of risk factor epidemiology.
Starting from such issues, four typologies of evidence in
public health are presented below.
Role of other confounding/risk factors
When a public health intervention operates on a single risk
factor of disease, such as air pollution for lung cancer and
diet for obesity, we know that other risk factors also act on
the disease. Therefore, an intervention to reduce the inci-
dence of a disease can work on one or more risk factors.
For example, to reduce the incidence of cardiovascular
diseases, it is possible to achieve effects simultaneously,
such as through health education about smoking, diet, and
sedentary habits.
Role of other diseases
Likewise, when it is the intention of a public health
intervention to reduce one or more risk factors of a disease,
it can also act on other diseases that have the same risk
factor or factors. An intervention directed at smoking, diet,
and sedentary habits can also influence other diseases.
Table 1 Characteristics of public health interventions
1. Length of the causal chain
2. Dual outcomes
3. Weakness of the causal chain
4. Role of other confounding/risk factors
5. Role of other diseases
6. Plurality of interventions
7. Context dependence
8. Words as causal factors
9. Low incidence of the outcome and length of the observation
period
10. Difficulty in statistical analysis
11. Difficulty in obtaining compliance from the study population
12. Difficulty in applying the RCT design
Fig. 1 Causal chains in clinical and public health interventions
Complexity and indeterminism of evidence-based public health 461
123
Plurality of intervention
Finally, to reduce a risk factor with greater efficacy, it is
possible to achieve simultaneous acts. The fight against
smoking includes health-promotion interventions, banning
smoking in public places, and increasing the price of ciga-
rettes. Figure 2 presents a simplified model and an example of
the complex interaction of causes and effects. Other available
causal models, such as the traditional web of causation
(MacMahon and Pugh 1996) and causal diagrams (Joffe et al.
2012), do not address the whole web or chain that starts with
one or more public health interventions. Thus, though the web
of causation is a finite, definite model, because it considers
only one disease, this model can be extended to infinity for the
extensibility of all three causal elements.
Context dependence
This characteristic has been extensively investigated (Pickett
and Pearl 2001; Dobrow et al. 2004; Jackson et al. 2005;
Kemm 2006) because public health interventions work in an
environment in which social, cultural, economic, and political
factors—as well as the competence of the operators—interact.
Accordingly, it is very difficult to apply the principles of
predictability and repeatability. In other words, and unlike the
case with clinical trials, the request to yield the same result
wherever and whenever they are carried out cannot be met. Of
course, within public health interventions, health-promotion
interventions are the most context dependent—mostly
because words, not drugs or equipment, are employed.
Words as causal factors
Unlike clinical interventions and other public health
interventions, health-promotion interventions, i.e., health
education, use words as causal factors to reduce risk fac-
tors. Thus, the first relation of the causal chain is funda-
mentally a bidirectional relationship that involves a deep
interaction between delivering and receiving the interven-
tion. In a broader sense, we have entered the realm of soft
science, such as psychology and sociology, where the issue
of determinism/indeterminism is still more difficult to deal
with and where the indeterminism (ontological or episte-
mological) of human actions and interactions is deeper than
in hard science.
When we need to assess the effectiveness on the disease
outcome rather than on risk factor reduction, an additional
three well-known items of more complexity are implicated.
Low incidence of the outcome and length
of the observation period
Though in clinical trials, a high incidence of outcome is
expected over a short period, the incidence of diseases to
be prevented in public health is much lower and is over the
long term. The major consequence, in the longitudinal
studies, is the need for a very high number of participants
and a very long period of observation.
Difficulty in statistical analysis
In general, following the definition used in this paper for
complexity, statistical models are (very) complicated—not
complex—systems, as they are deterministic and predict-
able. Indeed, if we repeat the same (very) complicated sta-
tistical calculation starting from the same initial conditions,
we always obtain the same result (predictability). Moreover,
the difficulty of applying and interpreting statistical models
concerns both public health interventions and clinical
interventions. However, for two reasons there is somewhat
more difficulty when public health interventions are con-
cerned. First, the more substantial role of confounders in risk
factor epidemiology makes it more difficult to establish
causal association. Second, the outcomes of public health
interventions yield, generally, only small differences
between the treated group and the control group, making it
difficult to obtain statistical significance (Buring 2002).
Difficulty in obtaining compliance from the study
population
It is well known that the length of the observational period
and the magnitude of the sample size are related to
increased difficulty in obtaining compliance and to a high
risk of sample attrition throughout the follow-up period.
The main consequence is the introduction of selection bias,
which contributes to uncertainty and unpredictability in the
outcomes.
Fig. 2 Interaction model and an example with public health inter- ventions, risk factors and diseases
462 F. Attena
123
From the above the last well-known issue is derived.
Difficulty in applying the RCT design
The wide discussion about this issue (Campbell et al. 2000;
Rychetnik et al. 2002; Dobrow et al. 2004; Hawe et al. 2004;
Victora et al. 2004; Petticrew et al. 2012) addresses the fol-
lowing questions: because the RCT design was originally
developed for interventions that are independent of context, it
is necessary for the public health intervention to incorporate
contextual information into the design of the RCT (Pickett and
Pearl 2001). Similarly, it has been suggested that in addition to
the outcome evaluation, a process evaluation should be
included. A process evaluation can help distinguish between
interventions that are inherently faulty (because of concept or
theory) and those that are badly delivered (implementation
failure) (Oakley et al. 2006); another way is to achieve a high
level of standardization of the whole intervention (Craig et al.
2008). When it is impossible to carry out RCTs, i.e., when the
unit of intervention is a community or when it is very difficult
to implement randomization or double-blind conditions, it is
important to look at and evaluate other forms of evidence.
Returning to the characteristics of complex systems, we
have seen that public health interventions, particularly
health-promotion interventions, are composed of a large
number of interacting components and by an intricate web of
causation. These components can produce self-organization,
retroaction, and emergent properties owing to human inter-
action between delivery and receipt of the intervention;
finally, they are poorly predictable for the above character-
istics, mostly because of context dependence.
Four typologies of evidence
As we have seen, starting from the causal chain when a
public health intervention is performed, it is possible to
carry out two levels of evaluation: the effect of the inter-
vention on risk factor reduction (first relation), and the
effect of risk factor reduction on disease reduction (second
relation). Each of these relations may be evidence-based or
not according to previous knowledge or the condition of
self-evidence. When a relation is evidence-based or self-
evident, it is useless in making an evaluation. On this basis,
the opportunity to evaluate neither, one, or both relations
arises (Table 2).
Evidence of both relations
Much environmental epidemiology is included in this cat-
egory. For example, water disinfection ? microorganism elimination ? infectious disease reduction; application of filters ? reduced dioxin intake in the atmosphere ? can- cer reduction. In both these examples, it is clearly unnec-
essary to carry out any evaluation because the causal chains
are evidence-based through the contribution of current
knowledge; in the second example, the first relation (fil-
ters ? reduced intake) can even be defined as self-evident. This typology is the only one in which it is possible to
speak of evidence-based public health.
Evidence of the second but not of the first relation
Evidence only of the second relation occurs typically in
health-promotion interventions. For example, health edu-
cation interventions to reduce smoking habits ? smoking habit reduction ? decrease in lung cancer incidence. The weakness of the first relation depends on the high context
dependence of health education interventions. In fact, we
may never be sure that a successful intervention in a given
situation is successful whenever and wherever. Instead, the
second relation is ensured by risk factor epidemiology. In
such cases, it is sufficient to check the reduction of risk
factors as a good result of the preventive intervention.
Table 2 The four typologies of evidence in public health interventions
The four typologies of evidence
I II III IV
First relation Evidence-based Grading of
evidence
Evidence-based Grading of
evidence
Second relation Evidence-based Evidence-based Grading of evidence Grading of
evidence
Evaluation of risk factor reduction No Yes No Yes
Evaluation of disease reduction No No Yes Yes
Evaluation by local public health departments No Yes No No
Evaluation by experimental research centers No Yes Yes Yes
Prevalent typology of public health
interventions
Environmental,
clinical
Health promotion Environmental,
clinical
Behavioral
Complexity and indeterminism of evidence-based public health 463
123
Evidence of the first but not of the second relation
This category occurs when the risk factor involved is still
putative. For example: relocation of power lines away from
towns and populations ? reduction in extremely low-fre- quency electromagnetic field exposure ? childhood leu- kemia reduction. The first relation is self-evident, whereas
the second relation is still uncertain. In these cases, it should
be necessary to conduct an evaluation of the real reduction
in disease incidence after the preventive intervention.
No evidence of either relations
The lack of evidence of all causal chains would require an
evaluation of both relations. For example, health education
to the owners of food stores and restaurants ? improve- ment in sanitary conditions ? foodborne disease reduc- tion. It is known that health education does not always
change behavior and that improving sanitary conditions in
food stores and restaurants is insufficient to produce a
reduction in foodborne disease in the general population;
however, this second relation is a little more consistent than
the first. This typology also occurs when there is a lack of
previous studies and knowledge about the two relations.
This model can be integrated with other models that
evaluate and grade evidence in public health (Briss et al.
2000; Tang et al. 2008). Such grading can be applied
separately to both causal relations.
The four typologies are useful in distinguishing pre-
ventive interventions conducted in local public health
departments and in experimental research centers. With
minor expertise and resources, the former types of insti-
tution can apply the first and second typologies, whereas
the latter types are also able to apply the third and fourth
typologies, which involve more complex evaluations of the
second relation.
References
Attena, F. 1999. Causal models in conventional and non-conventional
medicines. Medical Hypotheses 53: 177–183.
Briss, P.A., S. Zaza, M. Pappaioanou, J. Fielding, L. Wright-De
Agüero, B.I. Truman, et al. 2000. Developing an evidence-based
guide to community preventive services–methods. The task force
on community preventive services. American Journal of
Preventive Medicine 18(Suppl. 1): 35–43.
Brownson, R.C., J.E. Fielding, and C.M. Maylahn. 2009. Evidence-
based public health: A fundamental concept for public health
practice. Annual Review of Public Health 30: 175–201.
Bunge, M. 1979. Causality in modern science, Third revised edition
ed, 17–19. New York: Dover.
Buring, J.E. 2002. Special issues related to randomized trials of
primary prevention. Epidemiologic Reviews 24: 67–71.
Campbell, M., R. Fitzpatrick, A. Haines, A.L. Kinmonth, P.
Sandercock, D. Spiegelhalter, et al. 2000. Framework for design
and evaluation of complex interventions to improve health. BMJ
321: 694–696.
Craig, P., P. Dieppe, S. Macintyre, S. Michie, I. Nazareth, M.
Petticrew, et al. 2008. Medical Research Council Guidance.
Developing and evaluating complex interventions: The new
Medical Research Council guidance. BMJ 337: a1655.
Dobrow, M.J., V. Goel, and R.E. Upshur. 2004. Evidence-based
health policy: Context and utilisation. Social Science and
Medicine 58: 207–217.
Galea, S., M. Riddle, and G.A. Kaplan. 2010. Causal thinking and
complex system approaches in epidemiology. International
Journal of Epidemiology 39: 97–106.
Haddix, A.C., S.M. Teutsch, P.A. Shaffer, and D.O. Dunet. 1996.
Prevention effectiveness in health and medicine, 8–9. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Hawe, P., A. Shiell, and T. Riley. 2004. Complex interventions: How
‘‘out of control’’ can a randomized controlled trial be? BMJ 328:
1561–1563.
Jackson, N., E. Waters, and for the Guidelines for Systematic
Reviews in Health Promotion and Public Health Taskforce.
2005. Criteria for the systematic review of health promotion and
public health interventions. Health Promotion International 20:
367–374.
Jenicek, M. 1997. Epidemiology, evidenced-based medicine, and
evidence-based public health. Journal of Epidemiology 7:
187–197.
Joffe, M., M. Gambhir, M. Chadeau-Hyam, and P. Vineis. 2012.
Causal diagrams in systems epidemiology. Emerging Themes in
Epidemiology. doi:10.1186/1742-7622-9-1.
Karhausen, L.R. 2000. Causation: The elusive grail of epidemiology.
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3: 59–67.
Kemm, J. 2006. The limitations of evidence-based public health.
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 12: 319–324.
Kohatsu, N.D., J.G. Robinson, and J.C. Torner. 2004. Evidence-based
public health: An evolving concept. American Journal of
Preventive Medicine 27: 417–421.
MacMahon, B., and T.F. Pugh. 1996. Epidemiology: principles and
methods, II Edition ed, 26–29. Boston: Little, Brown and
Company.
Oakley, A., V. Strange, I.C. Bonel, E. Allen, and J. Stephenson. 2006.
Process evaluation in randomised controlled trials of complex
interventions. BMJ 332: 413–416.
Olsen, J. 2003. What characterises a useful concept of causation in
epidemiology?. Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health
57: 86–88.
Parascandola, M., and D.L. Weed. 2001. Causation in epidemiology.
Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health 55: 905–912.
Parascandola, M. 2011. Causes, risks, and probabilities: Probabilistic
concepts of causation in chronic disease epidemiology. Pre-
ventive Medicine 53: 232–234.
Pearce, N., and F. Merletti. 2006. Complexity, simplicity, and
epidemiology. International Journal of Epidemiology 35:
515–519.
Petticrew, M., Z. Chalabi, and D.R. Jones. 2012. To RCT or not to
RCT: Deciding when ‘more evidence is needed’ for public
health policy and practice. Journal of Epidemiology and
Community Health 66: 391–396.
Pickett, K.E., and M. Pearl. 2001. Multilevel analyses of neighbour-
hood socioeconomic context and health outcomes: A critical
review. Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health 55:
111–122.
Plsek, P.E., and T. Greenhalgh. 2001. Complexity science: The
challenge of complexity in health care. BMJ 323: 625–628.
Rickles, D., P. Hawe, and A. Shiell. 2007. A simple guide to chaos
and complexity. Journal of Epidemiology and Community
Health 61: 933–937.
464 F. Attena
123
Rychetnik, L., M. Frommer, P. Hawe, and A. Shiell. 2002. Criteria for
evaluating evidence on public health interventions. Journal of
Epidemiology and Community Health 56: 119–127.
Rychetnik, L., P. Hawe, E. Waters, A. Barratt, and M. Frommer.
2004. A glossary for evidence based public health. Journal of
Epidemiology and Community Health 58: 538–545.
Rychetnik, L., A. Bauman, R. Laws, L. King, I.C. Risse, D. Nutbeam,
et al. 2012. Translating research for evidence-based public
health: key concepts and future directions. Journal of Epidemi-
ology and Community Health 66: 1187–1192.
Susser, M. 1973. Causal thinking in the health sciences, 68–69. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Tang, K.C., B.C. Choi, and R. Beaglehole. 2008. Grading of evidence
of the effectiveness of health promotion interventions. Journal of
Epidemiology and Community Health 62: 832–834.
Tremblay, M.C., and L. Richard. 2011. Complexity: A potential
paradigm for a health promotion discipline. Health Promotion
International. doi:10.1093/heapro/dar054.
Victora, C.G., J.P. Habicht, and J. Bryce. 2004. Evidence-based
public health: Moving beyond randomized trials. American
Journal of Public Health 94: 400–405.
Complexity and indeterminism of evidence-based public health 465
123
Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.
- c.11019_2014_Article_9554.pdf
- Complexity and indeterminism of evidence-based public health: an analytical framework
- Abstract
- Introduction
- Evidence-based public health (EBPH)
- Complexity
- Indeterminism and unpredictability
- Complexity of public health interventions
- Length of the causal chain
- Dual outcomes
- Weakness of the causal chain
- Role of other confounding/risk factors
- Role of other diseases
- Plurality of intervention
- Context dependence
- Words as causal factors
- Low incidence of the outcome and length of the observation period
- Difficulty in statistical analysis
- Difficulty in obtaining compliance from the study population
- Difficulty in applying the RCT design
- Four typologies of evidence
- Evidence of both relations
- Evidence of the second but not of the first relation
- Evidence of the first but not of the second relation
- No evidence of either relations
- References
- Complexity and indeterminism of evidence-based public health: an analytical framework